allaire 1963 bare particulars

Upload: anonymous-pz2fxuyc

Post on 02-Jun-2018

252 views

Category:

Documents


1 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/10/2019 Allaire 1963 Bare Particulars

    1/9

    Bare ParticularsAuthor(s): Edwin B. AllaireSource: Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the AnalyticTradition, Vol. 14, No. 1/2 (Jan. - Feb., 1963), pp. 1-8Published by: SpringerStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4318430.

    Accessed: 06/08/2014 03:18

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    Springeris collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophical Studies: An

    International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 128.83.63.20 on Wed, 6 Aug 2014 03:18:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=springerhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4318430?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/4318430?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=springer
  • 8/10/2019 Allaire 1963 Bare Particulars

    2/9

    PHLOSOP

    STU IES

    Edited by

    WILFRID

    SELLARS and

    HERBERT FEIGL

    with the advice and

    assistance

    f

    PAUL

    MEEHL, JOHN

    HOSPERS,

    MAY

    BRODBECK

    VOLUME XIV

    Contents

    January-February963

    NUMBERS 1-2

    Bare

    Particulars

    yEdwin

    B.

    Allaire,

    STATE UNIVERSITY OF IOWA

    Does Modal

    Logic Rest upon

    a

    Mistake?by

    R.

    M.

    Martin,UNIVERSITY OF BONN

    andUNIVERSITY

    OF TEXAS

    IndirectSpeech Again

    by A.

    N.

    Prior,MANCHESTER

    UNIVERSITY

    Indirect

    Speech:

    A

    Rejoinder o Prof.A. N.

    Prior

    by

    L.

    Jonathan

    Cohen,

    QUEEN'S

    COLLEGE, OXFORD

    Baier's

    Test

    for

    Practical

    Rules Re-Examined

    byDavid Barry

    Lyons,

    HARVARD UNIVERSITY

    A

    Note on

    Commitment

    by

    LennartAqvist,UNIVERSITY

    OF

    UPPSALA, SWEDEN

    Lewis'

    Imperatives

    of Right by

    William K.

    Frankena,UNIVERSITY

    OF MICHIGAN

    A

    Note on

    Austin's

    PerformativeTheory

    of

    Knowledgeby

    Bernard

    Mayo,

    UNIVERSITY OF

    BIRMINGHANM

    Bare

    Particulars

    by

    EDWIN

    B.

    ALLAIRE

    STATE

    UNIVERSITY

    OF

    IOWA

    CONSIDER

    'this

    is

    red,'

    asserted

    rulyof a

    colored disc.

    Some

    philosophers

    claim

    that the

    sentence

    refers o

    a

    fact

    consistingof

    two

    (kinds

    of)

    entities,

    an individual(bareparticular)and a character universal),referred o

    by

    'this'and

    'red,'

    respectively.

    They claim

    further

    hat

    the two

    entities

    stand

    in

    the

    exemplification

    elation,

    represented

    by

    'is.'

    Currently,

    hat

    claimis

    1

    This content downloaded from 128.83.63.20 on Wed, 6 Aug 2014 03:18:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Allaire 1963 Bare Particulars

    3/9

    2 PHILOSOPHICALTUDIES

    widely rejected.Underlying he many arguments upporting hat rejection

    is a rathersimple idea which Russell

    once

    expressed: One is tempted to

    regard This is red' as a subject-predicate roposition;but if one does so,

    one finds that 'this' becomes a substance,an unknowablesomething in

    which

    predicates nhere

    . .

    Though awkwardly xpressed,Russell's point is clear: The individual-

    characteranalysis s at odds with the empirical radition. That is,

    if

    one

    claims

    that 'this

    is

    red'

    is a

    subject-predicate roposition

    n

    the

    sense

    that

    'this'

    and 'red'refer to

    unanalyzable

    ntities of differentontologicalkinds,

    then one has violated the Principleof Acquaintance

    PA),2

    a basic tenet

    of

    empiricism.One is not acquaintedwith a something which could be

    construedas an entity of a kind different rom red, except in the sense that

    this is a

    collection

    f

    the same

    kind of

    things

    as

    red,e.g., square

    and

    bright.

    The heart of Russell'spoint is thus that the individualsof the individual-

    character nalysisare unknowable

    n

    the sense

    that

    one

    is not

    directlyac-

    quaintedwith them.

    I

    proposeto explorewhether or not one can propound he individual-

    character nalysiswithout abandoning he

    PA.

    In

    particular,

    want

    to

    dis-

    cuss

    Bergmann's

    ssertion3 hat

    beingacquainted

    with

    a red

    spot,

    and noth-

    ing else, one is presentednot with justone thing but two, a particular . .

    and a character . . If I understandBergmann, e is maintainingprecisely

    what

    Russell

    denies, namely,

    hat

    one is on such occasions

    acquainted

    with

    an

    individualor,

    as he

    prefers

    o

    call

    it,

    a

    particular.

    His

    motivation s clear.

    He attemptsto reconcile he individual-characternalysis

    with

    the PA.

    Before discussinghis attempt

    it

    will be

    helpful

    to

    examinethe dialectics

    which

    give

    rise

    to

    the

    problem.

    will do that

    by commentingbriefly

    on

    two

    other

    analyses

    f the disc:

    (I)

    The disc is a collectionof

    what hassometimes

    been called perfectparticulars.

    This

    is red,'

    asserted

    ruly of our disc, is

    analyzedas follows: 'this'refers

    o

    a collectionof entities,one of which is

    referred

    o

    by

    'red.'

    This

    latter

    entity

    is such that

    if

    there were two

    red discs,

    there

    would

    be two

    such

    entities

    (perfect particulars),

    ach

    unanalyzable

    and

    numerically

    different

    rom

    the

    other.

    (II)

    The disc is a collection of

    characters

    universals).

    This

    is red'

    is

    analyzed

    as

    in

    (I), except

    that

    the

    entities

    are

    such

    that if

    there were

    two red

    discs,

    the

    two

    collectionswould

    have one

    member n

    common,

    .e.,

    one

    member

    which

    is

    literally

    he same.

    Each of

    these analyses

    encounters

    an immediate

    and,

    I

    believe,

    insur-

    mountable

    objection.

    Consider

    wo

    discs

    of

    the same

    (shadeof) color, size,

    shapeand so on.The objection o (I) is that it cannotaccountforthe same-

    ness

    of

    the discs

    since

    the members

    of

    the two

    collectionsare

    all

    unanalyz-

    able

    and different

    rom

    each other.

    In

    other

    words, hough

    both

    collections

    contain a

    member referred

    o

    by 'red,' (I) providesnothing they

    have in

    This content downloaded from 128.83.63.20 on Wed, 6 Aug 2014 03:18:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Allaire 1963 Bare Particulars

    4/9

    BARE

    PARTICULARS

    3

    common

    since the membersare

    unanalyzable

    s well as different.

    The

    ob-

    jection to

    (II) is

    that it cannot

    accountfor

    the

    difference,

    ince

    each

    collec-

    tion has

    literally

    he same

    members.4

    The individual-characternalysisencountersneither objection.That is

    its strength.

    The difference

    of the

    discs is

    accounted

    or

    by

    each

    containing

    a

    different

    ndividual;

    he

    sameness,by

    each

    containing iterally

    the

    same

    characters

    as

    in

    (II)). The

    individual-character

    nalysis

    hus

    allows

    one

    to

    solve the

    problemsof

    samenessand

    difference,

    at

    least as

    they

    arise

    in

    connection

    with things.

    Speakingmore

    traditionally,

    t

    provides

    a

    solu-

    tion

    to the

    nominalism-realismssue.

    Notice

    that a proponent

    of the

    individual-character

    nalysis,or,

    as

    I

    shall

    henceforth

    call

    him, a realist,

    explicitlygrounds

    (by

    means

    of

    entities)

    the

    samenessas

    well as

    the differenceof

    the

    two discs.

    There must be

    entities

    to

    accountfor the

    discs

    beingcalled the same

    or,

    less

    accurately,

    heremust

    be a

    shared

    omething n

    order

    to

    account for

    the same

    word ('red')

    being

    truly

    predicatedof

    'this'

    and 'that.'The

    objection

    to (I) is

    in

    fact

    some-

    times

    expressed s follows.

    Since the

    two red

    entities

    of

    the

    two

    collections

    are

    different

    and

    unanalyzable,here

    is no

    way

    of

    accounting

    or

    their

    being

    referred o by the

    same

    word ('red'). So

    expressed he objection s

    mislead-

    ing.

    Moreover, t tempts a

    defender

    of (I) to

    appeal

    mistakenly

    o

    a

    variant

    of the meaning-is-use octrine.

    The demandfor

    grounding

    ameness s

    at present

    suspect.

    The suspicion

    makes (I)

    seemattractive.

    Consider wo discs of

    different hades

    of

    red.

    In

    ordinaryanguage, red'

    may

    be

    correctlyused

    to

    refer to

    either.

    It

    appears

    that

    a realist,

    o be

    consistent,

    must

    also ground

    he sameness

    f the

    different

    shades.For,

    if

    he

    objects

    to

    (I) because t

    does

    not

    explain

    why the

    same

    word is used to refer o two

    perfect

    particulars,

    e must

    take

    seriously

    he

    same

    objection

    in

    the

    case

    of

    'red'

    when

    applied

    to differentshades.More-

    over,since each

    shade

    s

    simple

    and

    unanalyzable

    he

    ground

    (i.e.,

    the

    shared

    entity) mustbe of a differentkind.Thus,a third kindmakes ts appearance.

    For

    those of

    a Platonic

    stripe, his

    third is

    a

    transcendent niversal r

    con-

    cept.

    5

    Each

    shade

    s red

    by

    virtue

    of

    participating

    n

    the same

    transcendent

    universal,

    which

    is the

    proper

    eferentof

    'red.'

    Hence,either

    the

    PA

    cannot

    be

    maintained

    or

    we must

    be

    acquainted

    with ( intuit )

    concepts.The sec-

    ond

    alternativehas

    been

    unacceptable o

    those

    who embrace

    he PA.

    The

    realist hus seems

    doomed

    to Platonism.

    The proponent

    of (I)

    who

    denies the

    need

    for

    grounding

    ameness

    does not. This

    seemingadvantage

    hashad its effects.Recently, it hasbeen argued hat the root of Platonism

    is

    the

    mistaken

    way

    in which

    we

    sometimes ookat

    language. n

    particular,

    the

    very

    attempt

    to

    ground

    samenessreveals he

    mistaken

    belief that

    there

    must

    be

    a

    referent

    o

    justify

    the

    use

    of a word.

    Not even

    the referring

    se

    This content downloaded from 128.83.63.20 on Wed, 6 Aug 2014 03:18:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Allaire 1963 Bare Particulars

    5/9

    4 PHILOSOPHICALTUDIES

    of a wordrequires referent,or so it is argued.What holds in generalholds

    for 'red.'Hence, its use in referringo different hadesneed not be grounded.

    Thus, we are told, the samenessof the shades merelymeans that they are

    referred o by the same word. Moreover, t is claimed, even in the case of

    things of

    the

    same shade each exemplification

    f

    it

    is

    really

    different

    and

    unanalyzable.

    n other

    words,

    their

    samenessalso

    consists

    merely

    in

    their

    being referred

    o

    by

    the

    same word.6

    A

    defenderof (I) may thus attempt to dispose of the objection

    that

    he

    cannot

    account

    for

    the

    sameness

    of

    things by arguing

    hat

    the

    very

    at-

    temptto accountfor it is mistaken.The attempt,he holds, inevitably

    eads

    to Platonismwith all its horrorsof transcendent

    ntities.

    That

    shows

    why

    the

    use doctrinemay

    be

    attractive

    o a

    defender

    of

    (I).

    Consideragain

    two discs

    of

    the same

    (shadeof) color, size, shape,

    and so

    on. Supposethey are shownto you, one to

    the

    left

    of

    the

    other.

    If

    aftera

    while you are shown

    them

    again,you will not be able to tell which is which.

    In fact, you will not be able to tell whether he two you now see are the two

    you saw earlier.You can only tell that the two you now see have all the

    properties hat the two you saw earlierhad.

    In

    other words, taken as such

    and

    in

    themselves,

    wo

    perfectparticulars

    f the same shade cannot be

    told

    apart.That means that

    in

    this case at least the sameness s grounded.We

    know how the realistgrounds t. It remains o be shown that he need not

    therefore

    ground

    he sameness

    of

    different hades n

    order o justify

    he use

    of

    'red'

    for

    any

    of

    them.

    My realist akesadvantage f what the use doctrinehas taughtus, namely,

    (a)

    that from the fact that

    the

    same

    word

    is used

    to

    refer to two

    things

    it

    does

    not always

    ollow that the

    two

    share

    an entity. (Indeed,

    we could de-

    cide to use

    just

    one word to

    refer

    to

    green

    and

    red.)

    On the

    other

    hand,

    it

    does not

    follow

    (b)

    that

    they

    never

    do. The

    proponents

    of

    (I) rashly

    nfer

    (b)

    from

    (a).

    Their

    rashness,

    have

    argued,may

    be due

    to

    their mistaken

    belief that even

    (b)

    commits

    one

    to

    Platonism.Some things, our two discs

    for

    example,are

    the

    same shade

    of

    color. This is not a linguistic fact; i.e.,

    not

    merely he fact thatthey

    are

    referred o by the sameword.They are the

    same

    in

    that theyareindistinguishable

    s

    such, or, more precisely,one can-

    not

    differentiate hem by their

    color

    alone.

    Let us take stock. The problemof analyzing uch things as colored discs

    arises

    n the context of the

    realism-nominalism

    ssue. That issue, we saw,

    cannotreallybe handledby accounting

    or

    the samenessn the discs n terms

    of the samenessof words.At some point samenessmust be grounded n

    entities.

    To

    believe

    otherwise

    s to

    put upon

    the

    meaning-is-use octrinea

    burdengreater han

    it

    can bear. Thus,

    in

    our case, it remains he first task

    of

    analysis

    o

    single

    out the

    unanalyzable

    ntities which

    account

    for

    the dif-

    This content downloaded from 128.83.63.20 on Wed, 6 Aug 2014 03:18:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Allaire 1963 Bare Particulars

    6/9

    BARE

    PARTICULARS

    5

    ference

    and

    the

    samenessof the

    two discs.

    The

    second

    task

    or

    step,

    as in

    all

    cases,

    s to

    employ

    the result

    obtained in

    the

    firststep

    to

    explicate

    certain

    philosophical

    sesof

    words,

    hereby

    dissolving

    he traditional ialectics.

    The

    realisticanalysisprovidesthe requiredgrounding.Yet it is tainted. Like

    Russell,

    many

    philosophers

    claim

    that

    they are not

    acquainted

    with indi-

    viduals.The

    heart

    of

    the matter

    is whether or not

    Bergmann's

    laim

    that

    one

    is in

    fact

    acquaintedwith

    individuals

    bare

    particulars)

    s

    defensible

    or,

    even,

    whether

    t

    can

    be

    made

    intelligible.

    An

    obviousobjection

    s that the claim

    merelysprings

    rom

    the

    dialectical

    needs it

    satisfiesand

    is not

    borne out

    by a careful

    inspection

    of

    what

    is

    in

    fact

    presented.

    Indeed,

    Bergmann

    himself invites this

    objection.

    I,

    of

    course,

    have

    convinced

    myself

    that

    I

    am

    actuallypresented

    with

    two

    things.

    Yet

    I

    am

    loathe

    to restthe

    case

    on this

    conviction; or I

    am

    also

    convinced

    that a very

    major

    partof it

    is

    dialectical.

    One

    cannot

    but

    wonderhow

    one

    does

    convince

    oneselfof

    suchmatters.

    In

    the

    lightof

    what he

    himself

    says,one is

    indeed

    tempted to

    conclude

    that

    his

    conviction is

    dialectical

    rather

    than

    phenomenological, f

    I

    may so ex-

    press

    myself.

    If

    so, then he

    has

    abandoned

    he

    PA.

    Whether or

    not under

    the

    pressureof

    the

    dialectic he has

    actuallydone

    that is

    not my

    concern.

    The

    point is

    rather

    whether or

    not the

    description

    e

    proposescan

    be

    defended ndependentlyof the dialectics.

    Phenomenological

    escription

    s

    prompted

    by

    philosophical

    puzzles.One

    turnsto

    the

    formeras

    a

    prelude o the

    dissolutionof

    the latter.The

    dangers

    are

    obvious.

    One

    may

    think

    that one

    still

    describeswhen

    in

    fact one

    already

    argues.

    That

    makesall

    alleged

    descriptions

    uspect.The

    best one can do is

    elaborate

    hem

    in

    severalways,

    always

    n guard

    against

    hevarious

    biases hat

    mightcreep

    in.

    Once a

    descriptionhas

    been

    accepted, he

    puzzles

    must

    be

    solved

    by

    speaking

    commonsensically

    bout it.

    In

    the course

    of

    thus speak-

    ing

    about it, one

    maywell

    be led

    to

    reconsider

    t. After

    all, it

    was

    prompted

    by

    the

    puzzles.

    Nevertheless,

    one must

    not and

    cannot

    give

    awaythe

    game

    by

    maintaining

    hat

    the

    description s

    forced

    upon one

    by

    the

    dialectics.

    Bergmann

    n the

    quoted

    passage

    omes

    dangerously

    lose

    to doing

    just

    that.

    The

    most one

    could

    say is that

    the

    dialectics

    directs our

    attention

    toward

    what is

    presented.

    But it

    does not

    and cannot

    tell

    us what

    actually s pre-

    sented.

    A

    comparison

    may

    help to

    make

    the point

    clear.

    The later

    Wittgenstein,

    believing that the

    philosophical

    puzzles

    arise from

    the

    misuse of

    words,

    undertook o describe heircorrectuse.The misusesareengendered y what

    he

    calls

    misleading

    grammatical

    nalogies.

    Once these

    latter

    are

    recognized

    as

    such,

    the

    philosophical

    puzzles

    disappear.

    This is his

    basic

    idea.To

    speak

    as

    before,

    Wittgenstein's

    description

    of

    correct

    (and

    incorrect)use is

    the

    This content downloaded from 128.83.63.20 on Wed, 6 Aug 2014 03:18:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Allaire 1963 Bare Particulars

    7/9

    6 PHILOSOPHICALTUDIES

    preludeto his solution of the philosophicalpuzzles. Are then his

    descrip-

    tions unbiased?There is no guarantee.Nor is it reasonable o demand

    one

    beforehand.Wittgenstein'sdescriptionproceedsdirectly

    rom what

    he con-

    sidersa puzzleand thus indirectly romwhathe considers nillicit use.Thus,

    the dialecticsmay have influenced he description.But once more,

    the best

    one can do is guardagainstthe biases that may have been introduced.

    So,

    too, with phenomenological escription. n this regardall philosophers

    re

    in the sameboat. They all start romwhat they considerunproblematical r,

    as

    it

    is sometimesput, fromwhat they hold to be commonsensical.With re-

    spect

    to

    their startingpoint they must always

    be

    vigilant. One cannot do

    more;one must not do less.

    I

    return o the issue: Can the realisticanalysisbe defendedon phenome-

    nologicalgrounds? t will be well to distinguishbetween two uses of 'know.'

    First, there is the use of 'know' n which to know something means to be

    acquainted

    with

    it. Second, there is the use

    in

    which

    to know

    something

    means

    to be

    able to recognize t.

    In

    the second sense individuals

    as such

    or in

    themselvesare unknowable.Consideragain he two discsand

    the

    situa-

    tion

    in

    which you are shown them twice. Since you can only

    tell that the

    two you now see have all the properties hat the two you saw

    earlier

    had,

    it

    followsthat

    if

    each consistsof an individualand the severalcharacters

    t

    exemplifies, he individuals s suchor in themselvesarenot recognizable r,

    as

    I

    prefer

    o

    say,

    not

    reidentifiable.

    he

    characters

    re.

    To

    express

    he

    point

    differently,

    wo individualsare

    merely numerically

    different

    whereas

    two

    characters re

    intrinsically ifferentas well.

    Russell held that individuals re unknowable.

    A

    defender

    of

    the

    realistic

    analysismay

    take him to

    have

    held

    merely that they are

    not

    recognizable,

    i.e.,

    that

    they

    cannot

    be

    known

    n

    the

    second sense

    of 'know.'

    This, though,

    is

    not

    at

    all

    what Russell meant. Rather, n sayingthat individualsare

    un-

    knowable,he

    used

    'know'

    n

    the

    firstsense.

    In

    turn,

    I

    hold with Bergmann

    that

    while

    they

    are

    indeed

    unknowable n

    the

    second sense they are known

    in

    the first.

    Accordingly, cannot get awaywith just maintaining hat they

    are

    merelynumerically

    ifferent. must

    show

    n

    what senseone is acquainted

    with

    them.

    Not

    to

    recognize

    his

    obligation

    would be to

    confuse again the

    two uses

    of

    'know.'

    Nevertheless,

    n

    pointing out that individualsare not

    recognizable, .e., are merely numericallydifferent,one has arrivedat the

    heart

    of

    the matter.Individuals

    are

    just

    those

    entities which

    do

    groundthe

    numericaldifferenceof

    two things which are the same in all (nonrelational)

    respects.

    Consider once

    more the

    two discs. When

    presentedtogether, they are

    presented

    as

    numericallydifferent.That difference s presentedas is their

    sameness

    with

    respect

    o

    shape, (shadeof) color,and so on. What accounts

    This content downloaded from 128.83.63.20 on Wed, 6 Aug 2014 03:18:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Allaire 1963 Bare Particulars

    8/9

    BARE

    PARTICULARS

    7

    for that

    difference s the

    numerically

    ifferent

    ndividuals.

    No

    character, r

    group

    of characters

    an do that.

    Thus,

    to

    say

    that

    there

    are individuals s

    to

    say

    that

    things

    may

    be

    merely

    numerically

    different.No matter

    what

    de-

    scriptionone proposes, he numericaldifferenceof two things which are

    alike in

    all

    (nonrelational)respects

    must

    be

    accountedfor. Consider

    (IL).

    To claim

    that both

    discs are but

    collections

    of

    literally

    he same

    universals

    does

    not account for the thisness

    and thatness

    which are

    implicitly

    referred

    to in speakingof

    them as two

    collections.That is,

    the two collections

    of

    characters-if one

    persists n speaking hat

    way-are, as

    presented,

    numeri-

    cally

    different.Clearly,

    therefore,

    something

    other than

    a character

    must

    also be

    presented.That

    something

    s what

    proponents

    f

    the

    realistic

    nalysis

    call a

    bare

    particular.Or,

    perhapsbetter,

    that

    is their

    explication

    of

    'bare

    particular.'

    One

    difficultyremains.

    Bergmannclaims

    that

    in

    being presented

    with

    one redspot one is

    presented

    with two things.That

    maybe misleading.

    The

    most

    prevalentuse

    of 'two'carries spatial

    connotation.

    That

    is,

    if there

    are

    twothings then

    they are

    spatially elated.Yet

    exemplification,he

    relation

    obtainingbetween a character

    nd an

    individual, s obviously

    not

    spatial.

    Thus,

    the sense in which

    there are two things is

    merelythe sense

    in which

    there

    are two

    characters redand square)

    n the

    presentation f a red square.

    For redand squareare not spatiallyrelated.Nor arean individualand the

    character r

    characterst

    exemplifies. f

    one shouldinsist that the

    two char-

    actersare in fact

    spatially elated,arguing

    hat they

    are at the same place,I

    merelyask him

    what he

    means by 'place.'There is

    only one

    answerI can

    think of

    which

    would help.

    A

    placeas

    such is itself an

    entity. But, then, this

    answer

    makes

    places

    into

    bare

    particulars.This

    piece of dialectics s well

    known.

    Consideragain

    'this is red,'

    asserted rulyof a

    coloreddisc. To

    what does

    'this' refer?That

    it does referto

    something is

    obvious. It does not always

    refer

    o

    the entity

    referred o by 'red.'

    That is, 'is' in this

    utterancedoes not

    alwaysstand

    for

    identity.

    Hence, 'this' can

    only referto one of

    two things:

    an

    individualor

    a collection of

    characters, ne of

    which is red.8

    We know

    already

    hat

    the latter

    alternative ails, for in the case

    of two collectionsof

    charactershe

    membersof

    which are the

    same, the numerical

    differencebe-

    tween the

    two collections s

    left

    unaccounted or. The realistic

    analysisdoes

    accountfor

    it.

    Moreover, wo individuals

    re

    presented n the sense that the

    two

    collectionsare

    presented

    as numericallydifferent.

    That is

    not to deny,

    though, that individualsare merelynumericallydifferentfrom each other

    and thus not

    reidentifiable

    s

    such. That they are

    explainswhy

    they have

    been

    overlooked o often.

    I

    have argued

    hat one can

    propounda realistic

    analysiswithoutabandon-

    This content downloaded from 128.83.63.20 on Wed, 6 Aug 2014 03:18:14 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/10/2019 Allaire 1963 Bare Particulars

    9/9

    8

    PHILOSOPHICAL

    STUDIES

    ing the

    PA.Moreover,

    one

    can single out the bare particulars ithout

    using

    'exist'philosophically,

    hus

    avoiding he dialecticsof the

    nominalism-realism

    issue.

    In trying

    o do this, I

    described,

    r triedto describe,

    he sortof entity

    an individual s. Positively, ndividualsarethe carriers f numericaldiffer-

    ence

    as directly

    presented o

    us. Negatively,

    ndividuals

    re

    not rudimentary

    Aristotelian

    ubstances.

    Thus, they

    are not

    the sortof things Russell

    prob-

    ably

    had

    in

    mind when he

    denied

    that they can be known.

    To

    the

    sort

    of

    thing he had

    in mind Locke's

    phrase

    a something

    I know

    not what

    does

    indeedapply.

    To what

    I meanby an

    individual,

    t does not.

    To one who

    ac-

    cepts

    the

    PA,

    Locke's phraseprovides

    sufficient

    ground

    for

    rejecting

    the

    entities

    he

    speaks

    of.

    The individuals want

    to keep

    from

    being

    overlooked

    are

    not such

    entities.

    That

    is why one need

    not abandon

    he

    PA in order

    o

    maintain hat

    we are

    presentedwith

    bare particulars.

    ReceivedFebruary

    0, 1961

    NOTES

    'Bertrand Russell,

    An

    Inquiry

    nto Meaning and Truth (London: Allen

    and Unwin,

    1948),

    p.

    97.

    2

    The

    PA

    states

    that the

    indefinable ermsof any ontological description

    must

    refer

    to entities with which one

    is

    directly

    acquainted.Furthermore, an unanalyzable

    ntity

    is explicated o

    mean an entity represented y an indefinable

    erm.

    'Gustav

    Bergmann,

    Strawson'sOntology,

    Journalof

    Philosophy, 57:616

    (Septem-

    ber 1960).

    '

    Cf. Gustav Bergmann, Russell

    on

    Particulars,

    Philosophical Review, 56:59-72

    (1947). Reprinted

    n The Metaphysics

    of

    Logical

    Positivism (London: Longmans,

    Green,

    1954), pp. 197-214.

    6

    For a

    discussion

    of concepts,see

    Reinhardt

    Grossman,

    Conceptualism,

    Review of

    Metaphysics,

    14:243-54 (December 1960).

    'This

    explication

    of sameness

    may

    well

    explicate the

    Hatus-vocis

    doctrine

    of

    some

    medievals.

    '

    Bergmann,

    Strawson'sOntology, p.

    616.

    8

    As

    I

    have

    shown,

    the

    perfect-particular

    nalysis(i.e., (I) )

    is

    unacceptablebecause

    it does

    not

    account

    for sameness.

    Does Modal

    Logic

    Rest

    upon

    a

    Mistake?

    by

    R.

    M.

    MARTIN

    UNIVERSITY OF

    BONN

    AND

    UNIVERSITY OF

    TEXAS

    PHILOSOPHERS

    differ

    enormously s to just

    what

    they wish to include

    under

    formal

    ogic. Some wish to include

    the whole of

    mathematics,as

    devel-

    oped, say,within the

    simplified heory

    of

    types

    or within

    an

    axiomaticset